How to Explain the Direction of Time
Synthese. Forth.
Reichenbach explains temporally asymmetric phenomena by appeal to entropy and ‘branch structure’. He explains why the entropic gradients of isolated subsystems are oriented towards the future and not the past, and why we have records of the past and not the future, by appeal to the fact that the universe is currently on a long entropic upgrade with subsystems that branch off and become quasi-isolated. Reichenbach’s approach has been criticised for relying too closely on entropy. The more popular approach nowadays is to appeal instead to a particular low-entropy initial state—Albert’s ‘Past Hypothesis’. I’ll argue that this neglect of Reichenbach’s approach is unwarranted. A Reichenbachian account has important advantages over Albert’s: it correctly identifies the minimal temporally asymmetric posit needed to derive key temporally asymmetries and it offers a more adequate account of the record asymmetry. While a Reichenbachian account needs to be supplemented, it provides the right foundations for explaining temporally asymmetric phenomena and what we might ultimately mean by ‘the direction of time’.
Reichenbach explains temporally asymmetric phenomena by appeal to entropy and ‘branch structure’. He explains why the entropic gradients of isolated subsystems are oriented towards the future and not the past, and why we have records of the past and not the future, by appeal to the fact that the universe is currently on a long entropic upgrade with subsystems that branch off and become quasi-isolated. Reichenbach’s approach has been criticised for relying too closely on entropy. The more popular approach nowadays is to appeal instead to a particular low-entropy initial state—Albert’s ‘Past Hypothesis’. I’ll argue that this neglect of Reichenbach’s approach is unwarranted. A Reichenbachian account has important advantages over Albert’s: it correctly identifies the minimal temporally asymmetric posit needed to derive key temporally asymmetries and it offers a more adequate account of the record asymmetry. While a Reichenbachian account needs to be supplemented, it provides the right foundations for explaining temporally asymmetric phenomena and what we might ultimately mean by ‘the direction of time’.
Naturalism, Functionalism and Chance: Not a Best Fit for the Humean.
Forth. in Michael Hicks, Siegrfied Jaag and Christian Loew (eds.) Humean Laws for Human Agents, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
How should we give accounts of scientific modal relations? According to the Humean, we should do so by considering the role of such relations in our lives and scientific theorizing. For example, to give a Humean account of chance, we need to identity a non-modal relation that can play the ‘role’ of chance—typically that of guiding credences and scientifically explaining events. Defenders of Humean accounts (Lewis, Loewer, Hoefer) claim to be uniquely well placed to meet this aim. Humean chances are objective, and so suitable for explaining. Humean chances reduce to patterns in actual events in a way that limits the possible divergence between relative frequencies and chances. So, they argue, Humean chances can uniquely be shown to satisfy chance−credence principles. I’ll argue that Humeans have no special advantage. When used in scientific contexts, Humean chances must be allowed to diverge from the relative frequencies. So, when considering the scientific question of whether agents who align their credences to the chances will do well, it is merely probable that they will. This scientific use of chance undercuts the Humean’s claimed advantage over their rivals. This undercutting also points to a deeper tension in Humeanism: Humeans must either give up the aim of recovering scientific practice, or live with a disunity between science and metaphysics. While a focus on function is laudable, the motivation for being Humean must come from elsewhere.
How should we give accounts of scientific modal relations? According to the Humean, we should do so by considering the role of such relations in our lives and scientific theorizing. For example, to give a Humean account of chance, we need to identity a non-modal relation that can play the ‘role’ of chance—typically that of guiding credences and scientifically explaining events. Defenders of Humean accounts (Lewis, Loewer, Hoefer) claim to be uniquely well placed to meet this aim. Humean chances are objective, and so suitable for explaining. Humean chances reduce to patterns in actual events in a way that limits the possible divergence between relative frequencies and chances. So, they argue, Humean chances can uniquely be shown to satisfy chance−credence principles. I’ll argue that Humeans have no special advantage. When used in scientific contexts, Humean chances must be allowed to diverge from the relative frequencies. So, when considering the scientific question of whether agents who align their credences to the chances will do well, it is merely probable that they will. This scientific use of chance undercuts the Humean’s claimed advantage over their rivals. This undercutting also points to a deeper tension in Humeanism: Humeans must either give up the aim of recovering scientific practice, or live with a disunity between science and metaphysics. While a focus on function is laudable, the motivation for being Humean must come from elsewhere.
Caring for our Future Selves
2022. in Christoph Hoerl, Teresa McCormack and Alison Fernandes (eds.) Temporal Asymmetries in Philosophy and Psychology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
There are temporal asymmetries in our attitudes towards the past and future. For example, we prefer painful experiences to be in the past (rather than the future), and we prefer pleasant experiences to be in the future (rather than the past). While some take attitude asymmetries to be due to a deep metaphysical difference between the past and future, an alternative program attempts to explain attitude asymmetries in scientific terms. According to the Simple Causal Account, we care about future events more because we can (potentially) influence future events but cannot (even in principle) influence past events. In this paper, I’ll argue that this simple account needs to be enriched. According to the Enriched Causal Account I’ll defend, we care about future events more because they happen to our ‘causally later’ selves—temporal parts of ourselves that are ‘later’, given the causal ordering that underlies personal identity. This Enriched Causal Account recovers our intuitive judgements in a wider variety of cases than alternatives and fits with evolutionary explanations and empirical work. While the account isn’t the full story, it points to the need to pay more attention to our causal connectedness through time to explain temporal asymmetries in our attitudes.
Back to the Present: How Not to Use Counterfactuals to Explain Causal Asymmetry
2022. Philosophies. 7(2): 43
Online Article (Open Access)
A plausible thought is that we should evaluate counterfactuals in the actual world by
holding the present ‘fixed’; the state of the counterfactual world at the time of the antecedent, outside
the area of the antecedent, is required to match that of the actual world. When used to evaluate
counterfactuals in the actual world, this requirement may produce reasonable results. However, the
requirement is deeply problematic when used in the context of explaining causal asymmetry (why
causes come before their effects). The requirement plays a crucial role in certain statistical mechanical
explanations of the temporal asymmetry of causation. I will use a case of backwards time travel
to show how the requirement enforces certain features of counterfactual structure a priori. For this
reason, the requirement cannot be part of a completely general method of evaluating counterfactuals.
More importantly, the way the requirement enforces features of counterfactual structure prevents
counterfactual structure being derived from more fundamental physical structure—as explanations
of causal asymmetry demand. Therefore, the requirement cannot be used when explaining causal
asymmetry. To explain causal asymmetry, we need more temporally neutral methods for evaluating
counterfactuals—those that produce the right results in cases involving backwards time travel, as
well as in the actual world.
Online Article (Open Access)
A plausible thought is that we should evaluate counterfactuals in the actual world by
holding the present ‘fixed’; the state of the counterfactual world at the time of the antecedent, outside
the area of the antecedent, is required to match that of the actual world. When used to evaluate
counterfactuals in the actual world, this requirement may produce reasonable results. However, the
requirement is deeply problematic when used in the context of explaining causal asymmetry (why
causes come before their effects). The requirement plays a crucial role in certain statistical mechanical
explanations of the temporal asymmetry of causation. I will use a case of backwards time travel
to show how the requirement enforces certain features of counterfactual structure a priori. For this
reason, the requirement cannot be part of a completely general method of evaluating counterfactuals.
More importantly, the way the requirement enforces features of counterfactual structure prevents
counterfactual structure being derived from more fundamental physical structure—as explanations
of causal asymmetry demand. Therefore, the requirement cannot be used when explaining causal
asymmetry. To explain causal asymmetry, we need more temporally neutral methods for evaluating
counterfactuals—those that produce the right results in cases involving backwards time travel, as
well as in the actual world.
Time Travel and Counterfactual Asymmetry
2021. Synthese. 198: 1983–2001.
Preprint Online Article
How should we evaluate counterfactuals and abilities in cases of backwards time travel? We ordinarily evaluate counterfactuals and abilities by holding the past fixed and keeping the future open. Your decision to eat the cake may be counterfactually correlated with the cake’s being eaten, but not its being there in the first place. You might be unable to eat the cake given you had a dental operation yesterday, but not given that you don’t. Lewis, Sider and others argue that these temporal asymmetries persists even in cases of backwards time travel. Holding the future fixed amounts to fatalism, and is no different from doing so in ordinary cases. I’ll argue that these asymmetries should be given up in cases of backwards time travel. The past shouldn’t be held past fixed, because backwards time travel implies backwards counterfactual dependence. Parts of the future should be held fixed, because they’re in the causal and evidential history of the past. We need temporally neutral methods for evaluating counterfactuals and abilities to ultimately explain causal asymmetry in the actual world.
Preprint Online Article
How should we evaluate counterfactuals and abilities in cases of backwards time travel? We ordinarily evaluate counterfactuals and abilities by holding the past fixed and keeping the future open. Your decision to eat the cake may be counterfactually correlated with the cake’s being eaten, but not its being there in the first place. You might be unable to eat the cake given you had a dental operation yesterday, but not given that you don’t. Lewis, Sider and others argue that these temporal asymmetries persists even in cases of backwards time travel. Holding the future fixed amounts to fatalism, and is no different from doing so in ordinary cases. I’ll argue that these asymmetries should be given up in cases of backwards time travel. The past shouldn’t be held past fixed, because backwards time travel implies backwards counterfactual dependence. Parts of the future should be held fixed, because they’re in the causal and evidential history of the past. We need temporally neutral methods for evaluating counterfactuals and abilities to ultimately explain causal asymmetry in the actual world.
Freedom, Self-Prediction, and the Possibility of Time Travel
2020. Philosophical Studies. 177: 89–108.
Do time travellers retain their normal freedom and abilities when they travel back in time? Lewis, Horwich and Sider argue that they do. Time-travelling Tim can kill his young grandfather, his younger self, or whomever else he pleases—and so, it seems can reasonably deliberate about whether to do these things. He might not succeed. But he is still just as free as a non-time traveller. I’ll disagree. The freedom of time travellers is limited by a rational constraint. Tim can’t reasonably deliberate on killing his grandfather, certain that he’ll fail. If Tim follows his evidence, and appropriately self-predicts, he will be certain he won’t kill his grandfather. So if Tim is both evidentially and deliberatively rational, he can’t deliberate on killing his grandfather. This result has consequences. Firstly, it shows how evidential limits in the actual world contribute to our conception of the future as open. Secondly, it undercuts arguments against the possibility of time travel. Thirdly, it affects how we evaluate counterfactuals in time travel worlds, as well as our own. I’ll use the constraint to motivate an evidential and temporally neutral method of evaluating counterfactuals that holds fixed what a relevant deliberating agent has evidence of, independently of her decision. Using this method, an agent’s local abilities may be affected by what happens globally at other times, including the future.
Does the Temporal Value Asymmetry Support a Tensed Metaphysics?
2019. Synthese. 198(5): 3999−4016.
Preprint Online Article
There are temporal asymmetries in our attitudes towards the past and future. For example, we judge that a given amount of work is worth twice as much if it is described as taking place in the future, compared to the past (Caruso et al. in Psychol Sci 19(8):796–801, 2008). Does this temporal value asymmetry support a tensed metaphysics? By getting clear on the asymmetry’s features, I’ll argue that it doesn’t. To support a tensed metaphysics, the value asymmetry would need to (a) not vary with temporal distance, (b) apply equally to events concerning oneself and others, and (c) be rational and judged to be so. But evidence suggests the value asymmetry lacks these features. There are, moreover, independent arguments against its rationality. The asymmetry’s features suggest instead that it arises as an emotion-driven generalisation from a temporal bias concerning our future actions. This explanation points towards mechanisms that can play a role in explaining other instances where we generalise about the past and future, and why we’re tempted towards metaphysical pictures of time.
Preprint Online Article
There are temporal asymmetries in our attitudes towards the past and future. For example, we judge that a given amount of work is worth twice as much if it is described as taking place in the future, compared to the past (Caruso et al. in Psychol Sci 19(8):796–801, 2008). Does this temporal value asymmetry support a tensed metaphysics? By getting clear on the asymmetry’s features, I’ll argue that it doesn’t. To support a tensed metaphysics, the value asymmetry would need to (a) not vary with temporal distance, (b) apply equally to events concerning oneself and others, and (c) be rational and judged to be so. But evidence suggests the value asymmetry lacks these features. There are, moreover, independent arguments against its rationality. The asymmetry’s features suggest instead that it arises as an emotion-driven generalisation from a temporal bias concerning our future actions. This explanation points towards mechanisms that can play a role in explaining other instances where we generalise about the past and future, and why we’re tempted towards metaphysical pictures of time.
A Deliberative Approach to Causation
2017 . Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. 95(3): 686–708.
Fundamental physics makes no clear use of causal notions; it uses laws that operate in relevant respects in both temporal directions and that relate whole systems across times. But by relating causation to evidence, we can explain how causation fits in to a physical picture of the world and explain its temporal asymmetry. This paper takes up a deliberative approach to causation, according to which causal relations correspond to the evidential relations we need when we decide on one thing in order to achieve another. Tamsin’s taking her umbrella is a cause of her staying dry, for example, if and only if her deciding to take her umbrella for the sake of staying dry is adequate grounds for believing she’ll stay dry. This correspondence explains why causation matters: knowledge of causal structure helps us make decisions that are evidence of outcomes we seek. The account also explains why we can control the future and not the past, and why causes come before their effects. When agents properly deliberate, their decisions can never count as evidence for any outcomes they may seek in the past. From this it follows that causal relations don’t run backwards. This deliberative asymmetry is itself traced back to asymmetries of evidence and entropy, providing a new way of deriving causal asymmetry from temporally symmetric laws.
Varieties of Epistemic Freedom
2016, Australasian Journal of Philosophy. 94(4): 736-751.
When we deliberate about what to do, we appear free to decide on different options. Three accounts use ordinary beliefs to explain this apparent freedom—appealing to different types of ‘epistemic freedom’. When an agent has epistemic freedom, her evidence while deliberating does not determine what decision she makes. This ‘epistemic gap’ between her evidence and decision explains why her decision appears free. The varieties of epistemic freedom appealed to might look similar. But there is an important difference. Two rely on an agent’s ability to justifiably form beliefs unconstrained by evidence, and identify decisions as beliefs—either beliefs about acts (Velleman) or decisions (Joyce and Ismael). But when used to explain apparent freedom, these accounts face serious problems: they imply agents have epistemic freedom over evidence-based beliefs, and rely on a faulty notion of justification. Underlying these troubles, it turns out these accounts presuppose an unexplained apparent ability to form different beliefs. A third variety of epistemic freedom uses ignorance conditions instead (Levi and Kapitan). We appear free partly because we’re ignorant of what we’ll decide. Ignorance-based accounts avoid the above problems, and remain a promising alternative.
Time, Flies, and Why We Can't Control the Past
Forthcoming, in Barry Loewer, Eric Winsberg and Brad Weslake (eds.) Time's Arrows and the Probability Structure of the World, Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
David Albert explains why we can typically influence the future but not the past by appealing to an initial low-entropy state of the universe. And he argues that in the rare cases where we can influence the past, we cannot use this influence to knowingly gain future rewards: so it does not constitute control. I introduce an important new case in which Albert's account implies we can not only influence the past but control it: a case where our actions in the present are reliably correlated with several events in the present and past. To deal with such cases, we need to appeal to epistemic conditions on deliberation: being agents requires our decisions being epistemically undetermined at the time we make them. In a world with the past-hypothesis, this implies that deliberation will typically come prior to decision. Once deliberation in this direction is established, correlations towards the past cannot then be exploited for control. To explain why we cannot effectively control the past, we need to appeal to deliberation, whether as part of a defence of Albert's account, or used independently to explain the asymmetry of control.